English  |  正體中文  |  简体中文  |  Post-Print筆數 : 27 |  Items with full text/Total items : 109925/140876 (78%)
Visitors : 45967458      Online Users : 573
RC Version 6.0 © Powered By DSPACE, MIT. Enhanced by NTU Library IR team.
Scope Tips:
  • please add "double quotation mark" for query phrases to get precise results
  • please goto advance search for comprehansive author search
  • Adv. Search
    HomeLoginUploadHelpAboutAdminister Goto mobile version
    Please use this identifier to cite or link to this item: https://nccur.lib.nccu.edu.tw/handle/140.119/96760


    Title: 對預防理論刑罰正當化論據之批判
    Other Titles: Prevention Theories as Means to Legitimate Punishment – A Criticism
    Authors: Pawlik, Michael;鍾豪峰
    Pawlik, Michael;Chung, Hao-Feng
    Keywords: 不同意見書;民主可問責性;評議過程;司法獨立;司法權威
    Criminal Law;Theory of Punishment;Prevention;Deterrence;Correction;Retribution
    Date: 2010-10
    Issue Date: 2016-05-20 14:20:34 (UTC+8)
    Abstract: 綜上所述,本文認為,所有的預防理論只提及刑罰的效果而無法正當化刑罰制度。刑罰制度似乎必須完全根據「新」應報理論才能獲得正當化。
    Traditionally, the idea of prevention comprises two concepts: the concept of “negative prevention” (negative Generalprävention) aims at the deterrence of potential perpetrators, while the concept of “special prevention” (Spezialprävention) sees the purpose of punishment in correcting the perpetrator in order to prevent him from committing future crimes. Discussion in recent years, however, has circulated around a third variation of prevention: the theory of “positive prevention” (positive Generalprävention). According to this concept, punishment is a means to confirm the moral convictions of integer citizens. The article reveals that all theories mention important effects of punishment, while none of them offers a convincing legitimization for punishment. The concept of negative prevention conceives members of society as individuals that are foremost interested in personal advantages. While all individuals have an interest in the reduction of crime rates, the rational approach fails in view of the “free-rider” who acts most rational by demanding rules he himself does not abide. As the execution of punishment is not in the rational interest of the delinquent, the central act of criminal law is not covered by the fundamental premise of negative prevention. Additional considerations seeking to close this gap in reasoning fail: concentrating on the interests of the integer citizens would mean to exclude the perpetrator. Exclusion, however, is diametrically opposite to the idea of legal punishment. Pointing out that those who enjoy the advantages of an institution must also tolerate punishment as a sanction would mean to refer to the idea of retribution. Since negative prevention cannot legitimate the execution of punishment, it cannot be used as a concept to justify the threat of punishment: the standards for assessing threat and punishment must be identical. In the wake of the “reform euphoria” the concept of special prevention received a virtually medical shape according to which the purpose of punishment is to heal social defects. The state thus has to adjust “curing treatments” to the future dangerousness of individuals, thereby giving up the main characteristic of punishment: passing judgment on an unlawful act. In order to achieve optimal prevention the remedial treatment should even begin before an individual has actually committed a crime. This however would not be accepted by individuals who do not only seek protection by means of the law, but also protection against the law. A legal system is unstable as long as individuals conceive rules as mere items of calculation; hence, criminal law requires citizens who in general accept its rules as legitimate. The conceptualization of punishment therefore has to correspond with the normative convictions of the citizens. Surveys, however, suggest that the majority of the population has a preference for retributive punishment. The integrative effect of punishment would hence depend on an element situated beyond the concept of prevention. While the concept of general prevention is a theorem that—from the position of an external observer—describes a crucial function of punishment, legitimating punishment requires rules which—from an internal point of view— provide for a just execution of punishment. The concept of positive prevention itself, however, does not provide for such rules. As all prevention theories evince fundamental conceptual deficits, a legitimization for punishment has to be found on the ground of a retributive concept.
    Relation: 法學評論, 117, 347-395
    Data Type: article
    Appears in Collections:[政大法學評論 TSSCI] 期刊論文

    Files in This Item:

    File Description SizeFormat
    index.html0KbHTML2438View/Open


    All items in 政大典藏 are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved.


    社群 sharing

    著作權政策宣告 Copyright Announcement
    1.本網站之數位內容為國立政治大學所收錄之機構典藏,無償提供學術研究與公眾教育等公益性使用,惟仍請適度,合理使用本網站之內容,以尊重著作權人之權益。商業上之利用,則請先取得著作權人之授權。
    The digital content of this website is part of National Chengchi University Institutional Repository. It provides free access to academic research and public education for non-commercial use. Please utilize it in a proper and reasonable manner and respect the rights of copyright owners. For commercial use, please obtain authorization from the copyright owner in advance.

    2.本網站之製作,已盡力防止侵害著作權人之權益,如仍發現本網站之數位內容有侵害著作權人權益情事者,請權利人通知本網站維護人員(nccur@nccu.edu.tw),維護人員將立即採取移除該數位著作等補救措施。
    NCCU Institutional Repository is made to protect the interests of copyright owners. If you believe that any material on the website infringes copyright, please contact our staff(nccur@nccu.edu.tw). We will remove the work from the repository and investigate your claim.
    DSpace Software Copyright © 2002-2004  MIT &  Hewlett-Packard  /   Enhanced by   NTU Library IR team Copyright ©   - Feedback